1. Galileo's non-quanta concept of the infinite
It is precisely from the Aristotelian Simplicio that Galileo prompts Platonic praise of mathematics at the end of the first day of the Discorsi e dimostrationi matematiche, intorno a due nuove scienze, the Discourses and Mathematical Demonstrations Concerning the Two New Sciences. If he, Simplicio, could begin his studies once more, he would follow Plato's advice and would begin with mathematics. As he recognizes, itproceeds very scrupulously and does not admit anything as secure except that which it demonstrates conclusively1 (Galilei [1638] 1965, 8:134).
Preciseness and certainty are the distinguishing qualities of mathematics – Hilbert, too, spoke in this vein (1926, p. 170) – and we shall return to this aspect in connection with Leibniz. But what was the position of these qualitites when Galileo explained his theory of the infinite and the indivisibles during this first day of discourse?
Both notions are, as Galileo admitted repeatedly(Galilei [1638] 1965, 8:73, 76, 78) incomprehensible (incomprensibili) for our finite intellect (intelletto finito); they surpass the capacity of our imagination (capacita` della nostra immaginazione)(Galilei [1638] 1965, 8:83): the infinite as a result of its size (grandezza), the indivisibles as a result of their smallness (piccolezza) (Galilei [1638] 1965, 8:73).It is no surprise that he spoke of our human whims (capricci) compared to the supernatural doctrines, which are the only true and safe authorities being able to decide our controversies and which are infallible companions in our obscure and dubious paths or – rather (piu` tosto) – labyrinths (Galilei [1638] 1965, 8:77).
It is no accident that the appeal to the finite intellect and to theology, precisely in this connection, reminds us of Nicolaus Cusanus (Nicolaus [1440] 1967a, chapter 3) even though Galileo did not cite the Cardinal either in the Discorsi or in his other great works: this intellectual affinity will continue to be of great importance for us. We see though, as Galileo continued, “that human discourse cannot refrain from dealing with them”2, i.e. the infinite and the indivisibles (Galilei [1638] 1965, 8:73). In other words, that, which we do not understand, we would least like to speak of. For according to Wittgenstein we would have to remain silent on what we cannot speak about (Wittgenstein 1978, p. 115).
Galileo developed his theory by means of four mathematical examples which implied an analysis of the linear, the two-dimensional, and the corporeal continuum as being directly connected with a physical interpretation in the form of a corpuscular theory:
The paradox of the Aristotelian wheel with which he began and concluded the corresponding considerations and which he treated in greatest detail.
The equality of certain circular rings and areas of circles which leads to the special case of the equality of the circumference of a circle with a point.
A comparison between the sets of the natural and the square numbers.
The construction of a hyperbolical point system which leads to the special case of a circle with infinite radius, which degenerates into a line.
In regard to Leibniz we are mainly interested here in the first and in the third example. The famous paradox of Aristotle's “Mechanical Problems” deals with the question why two connected concentric circles, one of which rolls along a straight line, during one revolution cover equally long straight lines in spite of their different circumferences.
Averroes¨ had maintained that geometry cannot prove that this is the case. For this reason he was strongly criticized by Cardano (Cardano [1570] 1966, prop. 196):
Figure 1
“Whydid he not solve the difficulty, which is exclusively mathematical and rests on evident principles?”, he said in his New Work on Proportions. His fellow countryman Galileo, however, took the trouble to find such a proof. His fundamental idea was to understand circles as polygons with infinitely many sides (infiniti lati). This understanding enabled him to consider first the similar situation in the case of polygons with a finite number of sides, that is to say, the only case which can be understood by the human intellect. Galileo considered the problem twice. First he took the greater polygon to roll along its line and studied the resulting motion of the smaller polygon; later he took the smaller polygon to roll. Figure 1 refers to the second case. In order to analyse mathematically the finite and the infinite cases he used three pairs of notions corresponding to each other: The finite number of divisible sides 3 , which are quanta, of the polygons corresponds to the infinitely many indivisible sides of the circle, these being non-quanta 4.
The most important pair of notions is “quanti/non quanti”. Here, we find the key to the understanding of Galileo’s theory of the infinite. Arthur von Oettingen’s German translation leads the reader completely astray and enlarges the confusion by not distinguishing between the numerative and the quantitative aspect of the notions finiti/infiniti, which can mean both finite and finitely many, infinite and infinitely many. As to the “non quanti” it is not a matter of “infinitely small”. Only Goldbeck (1902) did not commit this error. But even he merely called the translation of “non quanti” by “infinitely small” questionable. All other modern authors like Bolzano (1851, p. 89–92), Lasswitz (1890, 2:45), Crew and de Silvio (1914), Mieli (1938, p. 218), Drabkin (1950, p. 185), Braga (1950, p. 306), Clavelin (1959), Struik (1969, pp. 201–207), Baron (1969, p. 117) have made the same mistake. Braga, for example, said explicitly: “Indivisible means the ‘actual infinitely small’5 ”. In truth, it is a matter of non-quanta. Indivisibles are non-quanta.
Galileo’s argumentation as well as his terminology refer loudly and clearly back to Nicolaus of Cues. In spite of this, the terminological connection has not been investigated before (Goldbeck 1902). In his work “On the Instructed Ignorance” (chapter 14) Nicolaus recommended the ascent from the quantum triangle (“triangulum quantum”) to the nonquantum triangle (“triangulum non quantum”), in order to better understand the statement that the infinite line is a triangle: If the base angles of a quantum triangle are assumed to be zero degrees, the triangle degenerates into a line: “As a consequence, you will be able to help yourself by making this assumption which is impossible in quanta (he meant that the angle opposite to the base becomes 180°) by ascending to non-quanta. There it is, as you see, entirely necessary, which is impossible with quanta” (Nicolaus [1440] 1967a, p. 17). Nicolaus underlined explicitly in “De coniecturis” (On Conjectures), that the coincidence of the contraries – of quantum and non-quantum, of straight and curved, of line and triangle – cannot be reached in mathematics. For that reason its proofs are the most reasonable and the most true according to reason (Nicolaus [ca. 1444] 1967b, p. 147).
Galileo, in proceeding in such a way, posed three decisive questions to himself:
1. How can we manage the transition from a finite number to infinitely many sides, from quanta to non-quanta, from divisibles to indivisibles?
2. What happens during this transition?
3. What are the differences between the respective notions of the three pairs mentioned in the first question?
1. The realization of the transition. The transition cannot be realized step by step by continued divisions of the divisible (Galilei [1638] 1965, 8:82), because such successive divisions do not lead to a last division. But the last division (ultima divisione) is exactly the division into the infinitely many indivisibles looked for, that is to say, into the infinitely many non-quanta. As a consequence, Galileo made use of an artifice (artifizio), which his interlocuters were requested to concede him (Galilei [1638] 1965, 8:93): The whole infinity must be distinguished and resolved at a single stroke 6 . Galileo’s procedure took into account the fact that a limit is not a special element of the sequence which converges towards this limit, and what is more, that a transfinite number is not a special case of the finite real numbers (Toth 1987, p. 176).
2. The occurrences during the transition. The transition leads into a new area, which was closed for mathematics until then, where the prevailing relations and rules lose their validity, and what is worse, their applicability. This difference should not be obscured. The transition is accompanied with metamorphoses (“metamorfosi”) (Galilei [1638] 1965, 8:85). When a terminated quantity (“quantita terminata”) proceeds (“trapassar”) to the infinite, “it meets with an infinite difference, what is more, with a vast alteration and change of character” (Galilei [1638] 1965, 8:83). And indeed: The corresponding notions result from each other by logical negations: finite becomes infinite, divisible becomes indivisible, quanta become non-quanta.
It is noteworthy that here, as when he compared the number sets, Galileo did not contrast finite with infinite, but terminated with infinite. This distinction between terminated and finite is to be found already in Nicolaus (Nicolaus [1440] 1967a, chap. 6) and we shall come across it again in Leibniz. It has been lost, however, by the translation of the two notions “terminated” and “finite” (“finita, terminata”) by one and the same word German word “endlich” (“finite”).
3. The differences between the respective notions of the three pairs. Quanta are divisible , they can be applied as measuring units and they are comparable in arithmetical operations. Non-quanta are not divisible, cannot be applied in such a way, and are not comparable. Neither the German nor the English translation does justice to Galileo’s careful formulations:
a) Relating to measurement. Let us consider the case that the larger polygon rolls along its line.
According to Galileo in the case of polygons of 100,000 sides, the straight line ABC etc. (see Fig. 1) which is traced out is traversed and measured by the perimeter of the larger polygon 7 . This straight line is equal (“e eguale”) to that straight line, which is measured by the 100,000 sides of the smaller polygon and in the course of which just as many empty spaces as sides are inserted. In the case of the circles, Galileo only said that the infinitely many sides have traversed the straight line 8 . The notion “measured” (“misurata”) could no longer be mentioned. The straight line traversed by the smaller polygon is equalized with that of the greater circle (“esser pareggiata”) by inserting infinitely many vacua non-quanta (“vacui non quanti”) between the infinitely many sides. “By imagining that the straight line is resolved into its parts which are non-quanta, that is into their infinitely many indivisibles, we can conceive them as drawn apart “in immenso”. The German version (Galilei [1938] 1973, p. 25) translates this as “ins Weite”, “widely”, the English as “indefinitely” (Struik 1969, p. 201). Braga even paraphrased “all’ infinito”, “to infinity”, as if immenso and infinito were equivalent (1950, p. 314). A bit later Galileo said that we could conceive of the first infinitely many components, since these are non-quanta, as being drawn apart “in spazio immenso” by inserting infinitely many vacua, which are likewise non-quanta.
Figure 2
The German text translates this as “zusammensetzen zu sehr großen Korpern”, “to compose into very large bodies” (Galilei [1638] 1973, p. 25), the English ¨ again as “indefinitely extended” (Struik 1969, p. 202). The intended sense, however, may well be that the indivisibles are separated from each other by a non-measurable space and that this is because vacua non-quanta, “vacui non quanti”, are inserted between them: A non-quantum occupies a “non-measurable space”.
b) Relating to calculation. Non-quanta cannot be added on account of their non being quantities. When deducing the law of falling bodies Galileo said that the aggregation (“aggregatus”) of all parallels contained in the quadrilateral A G F B are equal to the aggregation of all parallels contained in the triangleA E B (Galilei [1938] 1965, 8:208). For those in the triangle I E F are equal to those contained in the triangle G I A, while those included in the trapezium A I F B are common.
It is a gross misconception to translate aggregation by the German “Summe” (Galilei [1938] 1973, p. 158; Szabo 1987, p. 50) or by the English “sum” (Struik 1969, p. 209), which was usual even for Cavalieri’s “congeries” until very recently (see, however, Beeley 1995, p. 125; Koyre 1973, p. 341f.). In 1676 Leibniz defined the terminus according to Galileo’s view: “quod reapse divisum est seu aggregatum”, “what is really divided or what is an aggregation” (Leibniz 1980, p. 503).
c) Relating to comparisons. Non quanta cannot be compared because, unlike quantities, they lack the property of being measurable. As a consequence, it is not convenient (inconveniente), to ascribe characteristics to the infinites, to the “infiniti”, which we ascribe to “finite” and “terminated” things, “cose finite e terminate”. When he compared the sets of natural and of square numbers with each other, Galileo correspondingly observed that the attributes equal, greater, smaller do not occur between infinites, but only between “quantita terminate”, between terminated quantities (Galilei [1938] 1965, 8:78). Once more he contrasted infinite with terminated; he spoke only of infinites, not of infinite quantities, and on the other hand only of terminated quantities.
An “infinite quantity” (“quantita infinita”) would according to Galileo’s conception actually be a “contradiction in terms”, because an infinite lacks precisely those properties which characterize a quantity. Galileo’s application of a one-to-one correspondence between two number sets led him neither to a characterization of the infinite sets through comparison with the finite according to Dedekind’s definition, nor to a classification of infinite sets amongst themselves. As in Nicolaus of Cues there are no different infinites, and the Cardinal certainly provided the model for Galileo’s identification of the infinite number – on condition that there is such a number – with the unity (Galilei [1638] 1965, 8:83; Goldbeck 1902, pp. 77, 99).
Correspondingly, the Euclidean axiom “The whole is greater than a part” is not invalidated in the sense that the logical opposite is valid in the domain of infinite sets, that is, that an infinite set is smaller than or equal to one of its parts. Rather it is invalidated in the sense that it cannot be applied there, simply because there are no quantities which could be compared.
__________
1 che procedono molto scrupolosamente, ne` vogliono ammetter per sicuro fuor che quello che concludentemente dimostrano.
2 che l'umano discorso non vuol rimanersi dall' aggirarsegli attorno.
3 finiti lati quanti e divisibili.
4 infiniti lati non quanti e indivisibili.
5 ’indivisibile’ vuol dire ‘infinitesimo attuale’.
6 di distinguere e risolvere tutta la infinita in un tratto solo.
7 linea passata e misurata.
8 che linea passata da gl’infiniti lati.
|